Download the last draft of my book with OUP 2011 ("Why red doesn't sound like a bell")


ERC Advanced project "FEEL" website


PAST RESEARCH


CURRENT RESEARCH

CHANGE BLINDNESS DEMOS

PAPERS

Kevin photo June 2016

J. Kevin O'Regan


Laboratoire Psychologie de la Perception
Centre National de Recherche Scientifique
Institut Paris Descartes de Neurosciences et Cognition
45, rue des Saints Pères
75270 Paris cedex 06, France
Map

jkevin.oregan@gmail.com

website last updated  7 Feb 2018

In 2013 I retired as director of the Laboratoire Psychologie de la Perception (LPP), which studies human perception both in babies and adults. I then pursued a 5-year European Research Council Advanced project ("FEEL") on the sensorimotor approach to consciousness and "feel". With a group of 3-8 postdocs and assistants we developed the sensorimotor theory on five fronts, corresponding to the five workpackages of the project: philosophical, mathematical, color psychophysics, sensory substitution, and infant development/developmental robotics. We then continued the robotics/infant work within a FETopen project called GoalRobots.

Download my book on consciousness!

FrontCoverBook.jpgMy book "Why red doesn't sound like a bell" was published by Oxford University Press in 2011, and the final draft is available to download in pdf. It suggests a new way of thinking about consciousness (the "sensorimotor" approach) which dispels many confusions, and allows us to explain the "hardest" questions about consciousness: namely why sensations feel like they do (e.g. why red seems red to us, rather than green, or rather than sounding like a bell!), and why sensations have a feel at all. The theory is relevant to understanding what would be necessary for robots to really feel.

My Past Research Interests

After doing my first degree at Sussex University and the first part of my PhD at Cambridge in mathematical physics, I  switched my PhD topic to psychology to work on eye movements in reading, and moved to the Centre National de Recherche Scientifique in Paris. My most important early work was the discovery of an "optimal viewing position" for the eye to fixate in words. Recognition is fastest at that position and drops off to either side, making it useful for the eye to fixate there for efficient reading. From this I developed what I called a "strategy-tactics" theory of eye movement control in reading which explains why the eye goes where it does in reading. The idea is that the eye adopts a general strategy of moving a little to the left of the middle of the next longish word, and makes correction tactics as a function of ongoing processing if necessary. The theory is a compromise between the old "rhythm strategy" theory according to which the eye just plods along at a fairly constant rhythm without taking account of what is being read, and the (in the 1970's and 80's) fashionable theory according to which the eye reacts moment by moment, at every instant changing where it goes as a function of ongoing cognitive processing.

Ron with MudsplashWhat I am most cited for is change blindness, which I discovered with collaborators Ron Rensink and Jim Clark. Change blindness is a phenomenon where a person looks at a picture of a scene, but doesn't see enormous changes that occur in that scene when the changes are accompanied by a brief interruption like a cinema cut, a blank, or even small distractors like mudsplashes on a car windscreen. You can see more demos below. The phenomenon at first seems similar to the phenomenon of "inattentional blindness", where you don't see something that is fully in view because you are busy attending to something else. But change blindness is conceptually a different effect, since it depends crucially on the occurrence of a brief transitory event in the visual field that distracts your attention, instead of depending on the fact that you are consciously attending to something else.


My Current Research Interests

Today my main interest is one particular aspect of the problem of consciousness, namely the "what it's like" of sensory experience: why red seems red to us rather than seeming, say, green, or like the sound of a bell, or even like nothing at all.Color Spongeman

This so-called "phenomenal" aspect of consciousness is considered by philosophers to be the "hard" problem of consciousness, also known as the problem of "qualia". Other questions like the question of why we have selves or why we can become aware of things and use them in our rational actions and thought, are considered not so hard. Most theories of consciousness that neuroscientists talk about concern the second, "easier" form of consciousness. Brain mechanisms like large scale neural integration, feedback, recurrence or synchrony of neural discharges may be able to account for this "easier" type of consciousness. On the other hand, many people think there is a fundamental obstacle in dealing with the "hard" problem of consciousness. There seems to be a kind of "explanatory gap" between the physical mechanisms of the brain and the real, nitty gritty "what it's like" of sensations like red.

MovingSpongemanMy work on change blindness and on eye movements has led me to a new way of thinking about the "hard" kind of consciousness. In this, I consider that the feel of a sensory experience is not something which is somehow generated by the brain, but is rather a quality of how we interact with our environment. I have set out what I call the "sensorimotor" theory in various articles, and have just finished a book on the subject which should be appearing in the next year or so. The book is for  the general public and will probably have the title: "Feeling: Why red looks red rather than sounding like a bell".

MalikaJimSSThe new theory makes predictions and suggests breakthroughs in understanding consciousness which I have been exploring in the last years. Some of this work concerns what is called "sensory substitution", that is the possibility of using one sense (e.g. hearing) to replace another (e.g. vision), and so, for example, help the blind to see with their ears. I did this with Malika Auvray during her PhD in my lab.



Sensorimotor Color ManSome quite mathematical work to test the sensorimotor theory was done for his PhD in my lab by David Philipona and concerns the nature of color and space. David's work on color is particularly interesting because it predicts, better than ever before, well-known anthropologists' findings about why certain colors like red and yellow are considered more basic than colors like pink and purple. It also explains, better than previously, exactly which hues of red, yellow, blue and green seem "pure" to us. It seems to me that this work is getting very close to answering the age-old question of why red looks red rather than green. David Philipona's work on space is also very fundamental and has applications to robotics.

AlinePsychedelic
Other work done in my lab to test the sensorimotor theory was done by PhD student Aline Bompas. She confirmed my theory's prediction that the perceived quality of color should depend on eye movements. Finally, most recently with students Ed Cooke and Camila Valenzuela Moguillansky we have been looking at the "rubber hand illusion" and pain.



Papers to read and talks to listen to about the sensorimotor approach

Here is the slideshow of the talk on "How to make a robot that feels" that I gave in Zurich at CogSys 2010 in January 2010. It summarizes the essence of my approach to the problem of phenomenal consciousness, and includes material on the sense of self. And here are the videos (Part 1, Part 2, Part 3) of my talk on "Why red things look red: the sensorimotor approach to phenomenal consciousness" given in September 2009 at the Barcelona Cognition Brain and Technology Summer School.

My "magnum opus" is a rather long paper setting out the sensorimotor approach for vision and visual consciousness in the "peer review" journal Behavioral and Brain Sciences, where there were 40 replies from eminent scientists and my responses to them. Philosopher Alva Noë collaborated on the paper, but since then he has continued in a somewhat different, more philosophical direction.

An easy to read introduction to the sensorimotor theory of phenomenal experience is this slideshow, which is an expanded version of a talk I gave at the Association for the Scientific Study of Consciousness in Brussels, June 29-July 2, 2000, and at Bressanone, Jan 21-26, 2001. Another easy paper to read introducing the main ideas of the theory is this, written with Alva Noë.

My recent work supercedes the earlier papers by extending the sensorimotor theory to understanding the "feel" of all types of sensations, not just vision. Several papers on this were written with Erik Myin. This, this, and this are easy to read and introduce the concepts of "bodiliness" and "grabbiness" in order to explain why there is something it's like, rather than nothing it's like, to have a sensory experience.

The sensorimotor theory had its origins in a old paper I wrote which is often cited, and where I claimed that the visual world is like an "outside memory".
SpongeMan

Spongeman's Sensorimotor Manifesto is a wiki for collaborative work attempting to define as precisely as possible the terms used in the sensorimotor approach. Contributions invited! Why "spongeman"? Because in the sensorimotor approach, I use the analogy suggested by my collaborator Erik Myin of squishing a sponge in order to explain the "what it's like" of the feel of softness.

For a selected list of my papers organized by theme, see at the end of this website. For my complete publication list see here.


 

CHANGE BLINDNESS DEMONSTRATIONS 

(Feel free to copy these demos but if you use them in presentations or publications, please be so kind as to credit J. Kevin O'Regan and mention my website http://nivea.psycho.univ-paris5.fr)

Change blindness is a phenomenon in which a very large change in a picture will not be seen by a viewer, if the change is accompanied by a visual disturbance that prevents attention from going to the change location. The easiest way to demonstrate change blindness is to take a picture, and change some object in it. If you view the original and the changed picture in sequence, but with some brief visual disturbance like a blank field or "flicker" in between the original and changed picture, the change sometimes is quite hard to see:

With flicker the change is hard to see

If you take out the blank field however, then the change pops out immediately:

Without flicker the change is easy to see

Instead of using a flicker, it is possible also to use small disturbances like mudsplashes on a car windscreen:

A mudsplash also can mask a big change

You can also get change blindness by making the change so slow that attention is not captured by the changing element, as shown by this animation by my ex-student Renaud Chabrier. As much as 1/4 of the picture changes here:

Change blindness to a very slow change

If the change is part of what is the center of interest of the picture, attention is more likely to go to that part of the picture, and the change is easier to detect, as here:

The change is easy to see if it is part of the "Center of Interest"

The change can also be very difficult to detect if it occurs in a film sequence at the moment of a film cut. This is brilliantly shown by an ad by the London Transport Office warning that cyclists can sometimes be very hard to see if you do not happen to be attending to them:

Change Blindness in a film sequence

Daniel Simons at the Beckman Institute in Illinois has made wonderful demonstrations of this kind of thing occurring in real life. Some portion of road traffic accidents may occur because a small, brief distracting event (e.g. a windshield wiper or mudsplash crossing the visual field) masks a change (like a child running into the street).

Here are some more demos of change blindness, of varying degrees of difficulty.

Maoris (mudsplash)

Gunner (mudsplash)

Street (mudsplash)

Sailboat (flicker)

Nurses (flicker)

Big Fish (flicker)

Desert Fort (flicker)

Bus (flicker)

Barn (flicker)

Some other change blindness demos:

Flicker and mudsplash demos from  Nature article and supplementary info on Change blindness caused by "mudsplashes".

Larger versions of some flicker and mudsplash movies

Change blindness to very slow changes (needs shockwave plugin).

See also the Change Detection Database, and Ron Rensink's demos.

INATTENTIONAL BLINDNESS

Change blindness should be distinguished from "inattentional blindness". Inattentional blindness is a phenomenon in which you are looking at a video sequence or real life event, and your attention is so captured by the task you are doing that something totally obvious, perfectly visible, and in fact, something that you may actually be looking at directly, is not noticed. Transport for London has a demonstration of this on youtube.

This demo is actually a copy of an even more striking "gorilla" demo that was made by Daniel Simons, which itself was based on an experiment performed by Neisser and Becklen. You can find all this and more demos of inattentional blindness on Dan Simons' website, as well as discussion of the issues involved.

Inattentional blindness is at the basis of one of the main causes of road accidents: people "Look but fail to see" (LBFTS) some quite obvious and perfectly visible obstruction in the road.

My collaborator Malika Auvray has made a nice alternative version of Simon's "gorilla" video. You must track the coin and see if you can accurately determine which cup it ends up under. Only after you've done it, read here




Selected Bibliography

Sensorimotor approach:

O'Regan, J.K. (2009). Sensorimotor approach to (phenomenal) consciousness. In Baynes, T., Cleeremans, A. & Wilken, P. (Eds) Oxford Companion to Consciousness. (pp. 588-593). Oxford: Oxford University Press. [-] pdf

Myin, E., & O'Regan, J.K. (2008). Situated perception and sensation in vision and other modalities: form an active to a sensorimotor account. In P. Robbins & A. Aydede (Eds.) (Ed) Cambridge Handbook of Situated Cognition. (pp. 185-200). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [OS] pdf

Myin, E., & O'Regan, J.K. (2007). Phenomenal Consciousness Lite: No Thanks! Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 30, 520-521. [ACL] [IF=12.818]

O'Regan, J.K., Myin, E., & Noë, A. (2006). Skill, corporality and alerting capacity in an account of sensory consciousness. Progress in Brain Research, 150, 55-68. [ACL] [IF=3.253] pdf

O'Regan, J.K., Myin, E., & Noë, A. (2005). Phenomenal consciousness explained (better) in terms of bodiliness and grabbiness. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 4(4), 369-387. [ACL] pdf

O'Regan, J.K., Myin, E., & Noë, A. (2004). Towards an Analytic phenomenology: the concepts of "bodiliness" and "grabbiness". In Carsetti, A. (Eds) Seeing, thinking and knowing: Meaning and self-organisation in visual cognition and thought. Dordrecht: Kluwer. [-] pdf

Myin, E., & O'Regan, J.K. (2002). Perceptual consciousness, access to modality and skill theories: A way to naturalize phenomenology? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 9(1), 27-45. [ACL] [IF=0.918] pdf

gate io [-]

O'Regan, J.K. (2001). The 'feel' of seeing: an interview with J. Kevin O'Regan. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 5(6), 278-279. [ACL] [IF=10.981] pdf

O'Regan, J.K., & Noe, A. (2001). A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24(5), 939-1031. [ACL] [IF=12.818] pdf

O'Regan, J.K., & Noë, A. (2001). What it is like to see: A sensorimotor theory of visual experience. Synthèse, 129(1), 79-103. [-] [IF=0.477] html

Noe, A., & O'Regan, J.K. (2000). Perception, attention and the grand illusion. Psyche: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Research on Consciousness, 6(15), No Pagination Specified. [-] pdf

O'Regan, J.K. (1992). Solving the "real" mysteries of visual perception: The world as an outside memory. Canadian Journal of Psychology/Revue Canadienne de Psychologie, 46(3), 
461-488.
 [-] html  pdf

Change Blindness

Auvray, M., & O'Regan, J.K. (2003). Influence of semantic factors on blindness to progressive changes in visual scenes / L'influence des facteurs sémantiques sur la cécité aux changements progressifs dans les scènes visuelles. L'année Psychologique, 103(1), 9-32. [ACL] [IF=0.280] pdf

Blindness to scene changes caused by "mudsplashes". by J.K. O'Regan, R.A. Rensink, R.A. & J.J. Clark, in Nature, 398, 34, 1999.

Change blindness, by J. K. O'Regan, in Encyclopedia of Cognitive Science, Nature Publishing group, in press.

Perception, Attention and the Grand Illusion, by Alva Noë & J. K. O'Regan
PSYCHE, 6(15), October 2000

Rensink, R.A., O'Regan J.K., & Clark, J.J. To see or not to see: the need for attention to perceive changes in scenes. Psychological Science, 8:368-373. 1997

O'Regan, J.K., Deubel, H., Clark J.J. & Rensink, R..A. Picture changes during blinks: looking without seeing and seeing without looking. Visual Cognition, 7, 1, 191-212, 2000. html

Rensink, R.A., O'Regan, J.K. & Clark, J.J. On the failure to detect changes in scenes across brief interruptions. Visual Cognition, 7, 1, 127-146, 2000. pdf 

O'Regan, J.K. Thoughts on Change Blindness. in: L.R. Harris & M. Jenkin (Eds.) Vision and Attention. Springer, 2001, pp. 281-302. view Nov. 1, 1999 draft.
  


Color

Philipona, D.L., & O'Regan, J.K. (2006). Color naming, unique hues, and hue cancellation predicted from singularities in reflection properties. Visual Neuroscience, 23(3-4), 331-339. [ACL] [IF=1.411] pdf

Philipona, D., & O'Regan, J.K. (2008). Reply to Johnson and Wright. Visual Neuroscience, 25(02), 225-226. [ACL] [IF=1.411] pdf

Bompas, A., & O'Regan, J.K. (2006). More evidence for sensorimotor adaptation in color perception. Journal of Vision, 6(2), 145-153. [ACL] [IF=2.950] pdf

Bompas, A., & O'Regan, J.K. (2006). Evidence for a role of action in colour perception. Perception, 35(1), 65-78. [ACL] [IF=1.360] pdf


Space

Philipona, D., O'Regan, J.K., & Nadal, J.-P. (2004). Perception of the structure of the physical world using unknown sensors and effectors. Advances in Neural Information Processing Systems, 16, 945-952. [-] pdf

Philipona, D., O'Regan, J.K., & Nadal, J.P. (2003). Is There Something Out There? Inferring Space from Sensorimotor Dependencies. Neural Computation, 15(9), 2029-2049. [ACL] [IF=2.378] pdf

Philipona, D., & O'Regan, J.K. (2005). Perception multimodale de l'espace. In Philosophie de la nature aujourd'hui. Paris: MSH. [OS] pdf

Philipona, D., & O'Regan, J.K. (2005). La perception de l'espace, identification d'une faculté sensorimotrice? In C. Thinus-Blanc & J. Bullier (Ed) Agir dans l'espace. (pp. 151-165). Paris: MSH. [OS] pdf


"Filling in" the blind spot, visual qualia, and the theory of the "world as an outside memory"

O'Regan, J.K. Solving the 'real' mysteries of visual perception: The world as an outside memory. Canadian Journal of Psychology, 1992, 46, 461-488. view penultimate draft

O'Regan, J.K. The world as an outside memory -- no strong internal metric means no problem of visual acuity. Commentary in Behavioural and Brain Sciences, 1994,17, 270-271.

O'Regan, J.K., No evidence for neural filling in -- Vision as an illusion -- Pinning down "enaction". Commentary on Pessoa, Thompson & Noë, "Finding out about filling in". Brain and Behaviour Science, 21, 1998
 
 

Sensory Substitution

Voir avec les oreilles: Enjeux de la substitution sensorielle. by Auvray, M. & O'Regan, J.K.  Pour la Science, 2003

Auvray, M., Hanneton, S., & O'Regan, J.K. (2007). Learning to perceive with a visuo-auditory substitution system: Localisation and object recognition with 'The vOICe.'. Perception, 36(3), 416-430. [ACL] [IF=1.360]

Auvray, M., Philipona, D., O'Regan, J.K., & Spence, C. (2007). The perception of space and form recognition in a simulated environment: the case of minimalist sensory-substitution devices. Perception, 36(12), 1736-1751. [ACL] [IF=1.360]

Auvray, M., Hanneton, S., Lenay, C., & O'Regan, J.K. (2005). There is something out there: Distal attribution in sensory substitution, twenty years later. Journal of Integrative Neuroscience, 4(4), 505-521. [ACL]


Lack of translation invariance in vision

Nazir, T.A. & O'Regan, J.K. Some results on translation invariance in the human visual system. Spatial Vision, 1990, 5, 81-100.
 
 

Reading and "optimal viewing position" in words:

Lévy-Schoen, A., & O'Regan, J.K. Le regard et la lecture. La recherche, 1989, 211, 744-753.

O'Regan, J.K. & Jacobs, A.M. Optimal viewing position effect in word recognition: A challenge to current theory. Journal of Experimental Psychology, Human Perception & Performance, 1992, 18, 185-197.

Reilly, R.G. & O'Regan, J.K., Eye movement control during reading: A simulation of some word-targetting strategies. Vision Research, 1998, 38, 303-317.

Nazir, T.A., Jacobs, A.M., & O'Regan, J.K. Letter legibility and visual word recognition. Memory & Cognition, 1998, 26 (4), 810-821. view penultimate draft

Clark, J.J. and O'Regan, J.K., Word Ambiguity and the Optimal Viewing Position in Reading, Vision Research, 1998, 39, 4, 843-857.

Gautier, V.,  O'Regan J.K. & Le Gargasson, J.-F. "The-skipping" revisited in French : programming saccades to skip the article "les". Vision Research, in press. view penultimate draft

Vitu, F., McConkie, G.W., Kerr, P. & O'Regan, J.K. Fixation location effects on fixations during reading: an inverted optimal viewing position effect. Vision Research, 2001, 41 , 3513-3533.
 

Visual illusions

Ninio, J., & O'Regan, J.K. The half-Zöllner illusion. Perception, 1996, 25, 77-94.
 


Read here after having watched Malika Auvray's coin video:

Did you see the green pepper? Look at the video again if you didnt.



 
novopeacabe

samba capoeira
Some old documents about courses I taught
eXTReMe Tracker

View My Stats